From Newton to Einstein, Benjamin Harrow [most read books in the world of all time TXT] 📗
- Author: Benjamin Harrow
- Performer: -
Book online «From Newton to Einstein, Benjamin Harrow [most read books in the world of all time TXT] 📗». Author Benjamin Harrow
Einstein had become tired of assumptions. He had no particular objection to the “ether” theory beyond the fact that this “ether” did not come within the range of our senses; it could not be “observed.” “The consistent fulfilment of the two postulates—‘action by contact’ and causal relationship between only such things as lie within the realm of observation [see Note 2] combined together is, I believe, the mainspring of Einstein’s method of investigation.…” (Prof. Freundlich).
That the conception of the “simultaneity” of events is devoid of meaning can be deduced from equation (2) [see Note 4]. We owe the proof to Einstein. “It is possible to select a suitable time-coordinate in such a way that a time-measurement enters into physical laws in exactly the same manner as regards its significance as a space measurement (that is, they are fully equivalent symbolically), and has likewise a definite coordinate direction.… It never occurred to anyone that the use of a light-signal as a means of connection between the moving-body and the observer, which is necessary in practice in order to determine simultaneity, might affect the final result, i.e., of time measurements in different systems.” (Freundlich). But that is just what Einstein shows, because time-measurements are based on “simultaneity of events,” and this, as pointed out above, is devoid of meaning.
Had the older masters the occasion to study enormous velocities, such as the velocity of light, rather than relatively small ones—and even the velocity of the earth around the sun is small as compared to the velocity of light—discrepancies between theory and experiment would have become apparent.
How the special theory of relativity (see Note 4) led to the general theory of relativity (which included gravitation) may now be briefly traced.
When we speak of electrons, or negative particles of electricity, in motion, we are speaking of energy in motion. Now these electrons when in motion exhibit properties that are very similar to matter in motion. Whatever deviations there are are due to the enormous velocity of these electrons, and this velocity, as has already been pointed out, is comparable to that of light; whereas before the advent of the electron, the velocity of no particles comparable to that of light had ever been measured.
According to present views “all inertia of matter consists only of the inertia of the latent energy in it; … everything that we know of the inertia of energy holds without exception for the inertia of matter.”
Now it is on the assumption that inertial mass and gravitational “pull” are equivalent that the mass of a body is determined by its weight. What is true of matter should be true of energy.
The special theory of relativity, however, takes into account only inertia (“inertial mass”) but not gravitation (gravitational pull or weight) of energy. When a body absorbs energy equation 2 (see Note 4) will record a gain in inertia but not in weight—which is contrary to one of the fundamental facts in mechanics.
This means that a more general theory of relativity is required to include gravitational phenomena. Hence Einstein’s General Theory of Relativity. Hence the approach to a new theory of gravitation. Hence “the setting up of a differential equation which comprises the motion of a body under the influence of both inertia and gravity, and which symbolically expresses the relativity of motions.… The differential law must always preserve the same form, irrespective of the system of coordinates to which it is referred, so that no system of coordinates enjoys a preference to any other.” (For the general form of the equation and for an excellent discussion of its significance, see Freundlich’s monograph, pages 27–33.)
BY
Prof. Albert Einstein
There are several kinds of theory in physics. Most of them are constructive. These attempt to build a picture of complex phenomena out of some relatively simple proposition. The kinetic theory of gases, for instance, attempts to refer to molecular movement the mechanical thermal, and diffusional properties of gases. When we say that we understand a group of natural phenomena, we mean that we have found a constructive theory which embraces them.
Theories of Principle.—But in addition to this most weighty group of theories, there is another group consisting of what I call theories of principle. These employ the analytic, not the synthetic method. Their starting-point and foundation are not hypothetical constituents, but empirically observed general properties of phenomena, principles from which mathematical formulæ are deduced of such a kind that they apply to every case which presents itself. Thermodynamics, for instance, starting from the fact that perpetual motion never occurs in ordinary experience, attempts to deduce from this, by analytic processes, a theory which will apply in every case. The merit of constructive theories is their comprehensiveness, adaptability, and clarity, that of the theories of principle, their logical perfection, and the security of their foundation.
The theory of relativity is a theory of principle. To understand it, the principles on which it rests must be grasped. But before stating these it is necessary to point out that the theory of relativity is like a house with two separate stories, the special relativity theory and the general theory of relativity.
Since the time of the ancient Greeks it has been well known that in describing the motion of a body we must refer to another body. The motion of a railway train is described with reference to the ground, of a planet with reference to the total assemblage of visible fixed stars. In physics the bodies to which motions are spatially referred are termed systems of coordinates. The laws of mechanics of Galileo and Newton can be formulated only by using a system of coordinates.
The state of motion of a system of coordinates can not be chosen arbitrarily if the laws of mechanics are to hold good (it must be free from twisting and from acceleration). The system of coordinates employed in mechanics is called an inertia-system. The state of motion of an inertia-system, so far as mechanics are concerned, is not restricted by nature to one condition. The condition in the following proposition suffices; a system of coordinates moving in the same direction and at the same rate as a system of inertia is itself a system of inertia. The special relativity theory is therefore the application of the following proposition to any natural process: “Every law of nature which holds good with respect to a coordinate system K must also hold good for any other system K′ provided that K and K′ are in uniform movement of translation.”
The second principle on which the special relativity theory rests is that of the constancy of the velocity of light in a vacuum. Light in a vacuum has a definite and constant velocity, independent of the velocity of its source. Physicists owe their confidence in this proposition to the Maxwell-Lorentz theory of electro-dynamics.
The two principles which I have mentioned have received strong experimental confirmation, but do not seem to be logically compatible. The special relativity theory achieved their logical reconciliation by making a change in kinematics, that is to say, in the doctrine of the physical laws of space and time. It became evident that a statement of the coincidence of two events could have a meaning only in connection with a system of coordinates, that the mass of bodies and the rate of movement of clocks must depend on their state of motion with regard to the coordinates.
The Older Physics.—But the older physics, including the laws of motion of Galileo and Newton, clashed with the relativistic kinematics that I have indicated. The latter gave origin to certain generalized mathematical conditions with which the laws of nature would have to conform if the two fundamental principles were compatible. Physics had to be modified. The most notable change was a new law of motion for (very rapidly) moving mass-points, and this soon came to be verified in the case of electrically-laden particles. The most important result of the special relativity system concerned the inert mass of a material system. It became evident that the inertia of such a system must depend on its energy-content, so that we were driven to the conception that inert mass was nothing else than latent energy. The doctrine of the conservation of mass lost its independence and became merged in the doctrine of conservation of energy.
The special relativity theory which was simply a systematic extension of the electro-dynamics of Maxwell and Lorentz, had consequences which reached beyond itself. Must the independence of physical laws with regard to a system of coordinates be limited to systems of coordinates in uniform movement of translation with regard to one another? What has nature to do with the coordinate systems that we propose and with their motions? Although it may be necessary for our descriptions of nature to employ systems of coordinates that we have selected arbitrarily, the choice should not be limited in any way so far as their state of motion is concerned. (General theory of relativity.) The application of this general theory of relativity was found to be in conflict with a well-known experiment, according to which it appeared that the weight and the inertia of a body depended on the same constants (identity of inert and heavy masses). Consider the case of a system of coordinates which is conceived as being in stable rotation relative to a system of inertia in the Newtonian sense. The forces which, relatively to this system, are centrifugal must, in the Newtonian sense, be attributed to inertia. But these centrifugal forces are, like gravitation, proportional to the mass of the bodies. Is it not, then, possible to regard the system of coordinates as at rest, and the centrifugal forces as gravitational? The interpretation seemed obvious, but classical mechanics forbade it.
This slight sketch indicates how a generalized theory of relativity must include the laws of gravitation, and actual pursuit of the conception has justified the hope. But the way was harder than was expected, because it contradicted Euclidian geometry. In other words, the laws according to which material bodies are arranged in space do not exactly agree with the laws of space prescribed by the Euclidian geometry of solids. This is what is meant by the phrase “a warp in space.” The fundamental concepts “straight,” “plane,” etc., accordingly lose their exact meaning in physics.
In the generalized theory of relativity, the doctrine of space and time, kinematics, is no longer one of the absolute foundations of general physics. The geometrical states of bodies and the rates of clocks depend in the first place on their gravitational fields, which again are produced by the material system concerned.
Thus the new theory of gravitation diverges widely from that of Newton with respect to its basal principle. But in practical application the two agree so closely that it has been difficult to find cases in which the actual differences could be subjected to observation. As yet only the following have been suggested:
1. The distortion of the oval orbits of planets round the sun (confirmed in the case of the planet Mercury).
2. The deviation of light-rays in a gravitational field (confirmed by the English Solar Eclipse expedition).
3. The shifting of spectral lines towards the red end of the spectrum in the case of light coming to us from stars of appreciable mass (not yet confirmed).
The great attraction of the theory is its logical consistency. If any deduction from it
Comments (0)