The Ego and his Own, Max Stirner [ebook reader for surface pro .txt] 📗
- Author: Max Stirner
- Performer: -
Book online «The Ego and his Own, Max Stirner [ebook reader for surface pro .txt] 📗». Author Max Stirner
personal invasion of another's sphere revolts the civic sense; if the
citizen sees that one is dependent on the humor, the pleasure, the will of a
man as individual (i.e. as not as authorized by a "higher power"), at once
he brings his liberalism to the front and shrieks about "arbitrariness." In
fine, the citizen asserts his freedom from what is called orders
(ordonnance): "No one has any business to give me -- orders!" Orders
carries the idea that what I am to do is another man's will, while law does
not express a personal authority of another. The liberty of the commonalty is
liberty or independence from the will of another person, so-called personal or
individual liberty; for being personally free means being only so free that no
other person can dispose of mine, or that what I may or may not do does not
depend on the personal decree of another. The liberty of the press, e. g.,
is such a liberty of liberalism, liberalism fighting only against the coercion
of the censorship as that of personal wilfulness, but otherwise showing itself
extremely inclined and willing to tyrannize over the press by "press laws";
i.e. the civic liberals want liberty of writing for themselves; for, as
they are law-abiding, their writings will not bring them under the law. Only
liberal matter, i.e. only lawful matter, is to be allowed to be printed;
otherwise the "press laws" threaten "press-penalties." If one sees personal
liberty assured, one does not notice at all how, if a new issue happens to
arise, the most glaring unfreedom becomes dominant. For one is rid of orders
indeed, and "no one has any business to give us orders," but one has become so
much the more submissive to the -- law. One is enthralled now in due legal
form.
In the citizen-State there are only "free people," who are compelled to
thousands of things (e. g. to deference, to a confession of faith, etc.).
But what does that amount to? Why, it is only the -- State, the law, not any
man, that compels them!
What does the commonalty mean by inveighing against every personal order,
i.e. every order not founded on the "cause," on "reason"? It is simply
fighting in the interest of the "cause"(67) against the dominion of "persons"!
But the mind's cause is the rational, good, lawful, etc.; that is the "good
cause." The commonalty wants an impersonal ruler.
Furthermore, if the principle is this, that only the cause is to rule man --
to wit, the cause of morality, the cause of legality, etc., then no personal
balking of one by the other may be authorized either (as formerly, e. g. the
commoner was balked of the aristocratic offices, the aristocrat of common
mechanical trades, etc.); free competition must exist. Only through the
thing(68) can one balk another (e. g. the rich man balking the impecunious
man by money, a thing), not as a person. Henceforth only one lordship, the
lordship of the State, is admitted; personally no one is any longer lord of
another. Even at birth the children belong to the State, and to the parents
only in the name of the State, which e. g. does not allow infanticide,
demands their baptism etc.
But all the State's children, furthermore, are of quite equal account in its
eyes ("civic or political equality"), and they may see to it themselves how
they get along with each other; they may compete.
Free competition means nothing else than that every one can present himself,
assert himself, fight, against another. Of course the feudal party set itself
against this, as its existence depended on an absence of competition. The
contests in the time of the Restoration in France had no other substance than
this -- that the bourgeoisie was struggling for free competition, and the
feudalists were seeking to bring back the guild system.
Now, free competition has won, and against the guild system it had to win.
(See below for the further discussion.)
If the Revolution ended in a reaction, this only showed what the Revolution
really was. For every effort arrives at reaction when it *comes to discreet
reflection*, and storms forward in the original action only so long as it is
an intoxication, an "indiscretion." "Discretion" will always be the cue of
the reaction, because discretion sets limits, and liberates what was really
wanted, i. e., the principle, from the initial "unbridledness" and
"unrestrainedness." Wild young fellows, bumptious students, who set aside all
considerations, are really Philistines, since with them, as with the latter,
considerations form the substance of their conduct; only that as swaggerers
they are mutinous against considerations and in negative relations to them,
but as Philistines, later, they give themselves up to considerations and have
positive relations to them. In both cases all their doing and thinking turns
upon "considerations," but the Philistine is reactionary in relation to the
student; he is the wild fellow come to discreet reflection, as the latter is
the unreflecting Philistine. Daily experience confirms the truth of this
transformation, and shows how the swaggerers turn to Philistines in turning
gray.
So, too, the so-called reaction in Germany gives proof that it was only the
discreet continuation of the warlike jubilation of liberty.
The Revolution was not directed against the established, but against the
establishment in question, against a particular establishment. It did away
with this ruler, not with the ruler -- on the contrary, the French were
ruled most inexorably; it killed the old vicious rulers, but wanted to confer
on the virtuous ones a securely established position, i. e., it simply set
virtue in the place of vice. (Vice and virtue, again, are on their part
distinguished from each other only as a wild young fellow from a Philistine.)
Etc.
To this day the revolutionary principle has gone no farther than to assail
only one or another particular establishment, i.e. be reformatory. Much
as may be improved, strongly as "discreet progress" may be adhered to,
always there is only a new master set in the old one's place, and the
overturning is a -- building up. We are still at the distinction of the young
Philistine from the old one. The Revolution began in bourgeois fashion with
the uprising of the third estate, the middle class; in bourgeois fashion it
dries away. It was not the individual man -- and he alone is Man -- that
became free, but the citizen, the citoyen, the political man, who for
that very reason is not Man but a specimen of the human species, and more
particularly a specimen of the species Citizen, a free citizen.
In the Revolution it was not the individual who acted so as to affect the
world's history, but a people; the nation, the sovereign nation, wanted to
effect everything. A fancied I, an idea, e. g. the nation is, appears
acting; the individuals contribute themselves as tools of this idea, and act
as "citizens."
The commonalty has its power, and at the same time its limits, in the
fundamental law of the State, in a charter, in a legitimate(69) or
"just"(70) prince who himself is guided, and rules, according to "rational
laws," in short, in legality. The period of the bourgeoisie is ruled by
the British spirit of legality. An assembly of provincial estates, e. g. is
ever recalling that its authorization goes only so and so far, and that it is
called at all only through favor and can be thrown out again through disfavor.
It is always reminding itself of its -- vocation. It is certainly not to be
denied that my father begot me; but, now that I am once begotten, surely his
purposes in begetting do not concern me a bit and, whatever he may have
called me to, I do what I myself will. Therefore even a called assembly of
estates, the French assembly in the beginning of the Revolution, recognized
quite rightly that it was independent of the caller. It existed, and would
have been stupid if it did not avail itself of the right of existence, but
fancied itself dependent as on a father. The called one no longer has to ask
"what did the caller want when he created me?" but "what do I want after I
have once followed the call?" Not the caller, not the constituents, not the
charter according to which their meeting was called out, nothing will be to
him a sacred, inviolable power. He is authorized for everything that is in
his power; he will know no restrictive "authorization," will not want to be
loyal. This, if any such thing could be expected from chambers at all, would
give a completely egoistic chamber, severed from all navel-string and
without consideration. But chambers are always devout, and therefore one
cannot be surprised if so much half-way or undecided,
i. e., hypocritical, "egoism" parades in them.
The members of the estates are to remain within the limits that are traced
for them by the charter, by the king's will, etc. If they will not or can not
do that, then they are to "step out." What dutiful man could act otherwise,
could put himself, his conviction, and his will as the first thing? Who
could be so immoral as to want to assert himself, even if the body corporate
and everything should go to ruin over it? People keep carefully within the
limits of their authorization; of course one must remain within the limits
of his power anyhow, because no one can do more than he can. "My power, or,
if it be so, powerlessness, be my sole limit, but authorizations only
restraining -- precepts? Should I profess this all-subversive view? No, I am a
-- law-abiding citizen!"
The commonalty professes a morality which is most closely connected with its
essence. The first demand of this morality is to the effect that one should
carry on a solid business, an honourable trade, lead a moral life. Immoral, to
it, is the sharper, the, demirep, the thief, robber, and murderer, the
gamester, the penniless man without a situation, the frivolous man. The
doughty commoner designates the feeling against these "immoral" people as his
"deepest indignation."
All these lack settlement, the solid quality of business, a solid, seemly
life, a fixed income, etc.; in short, they belong, because their existence
does not rest on a secure basis to the dangerous "individuals or isolated
persons," to the dangerous proletariat; they are "individual bawlers" who
offer no "guarantee" and have "nothing to lose," and so nothing to risk. The
forming of family ties, e. g., binds a man: he who is bound furnishes
security, can be taken hold of; not so the street-walker. The
Comments (0)