Sixteen Experimental Investigations from the Harvard Psychological Laboratory, Hugo Münsterberg [top fiction books of all time TXT] 📗
- Author: Hugo Münsterberg
- Performer: -
Book online «Sixteen Experimental Investigations from the Harvard Psychological Laboratory, Hugo Münsterberg [top fiction books of all time TXT] 📗». Author Hugo Münsterberg
has come to rest on a new fixation point (by supposition to the right
of the old), we should expect the streak to be localized to the left
of this, that is, to the right of the former fixation-point. In order
to be projected, a retinal image has to be localized with reference to
some point, generally the fixation-point of the eyes; and it is
therefore clear that when two such fixation-points are involved, the
localization will be ambiguous if for any reason the central apparatus
does not clearly determine which shall be the point of reference. With
regard to the oppositely moving streak Mach says:[9] “The streak is,
of course, an after-image, which comes to consciousness only on, or
shortly before, the completion of the eye-movement, nevertheless with
positional values which correspond, remarkably enough, not to the
later but to the earlier position and innervation of the eyes.” Mach
does not further attempt to explain the phenomenon.
[8] Mach, Ernst, ‘Beiträge zur Analyze der Empfindungen,’ Jena,
1886.[9] Mach, op. citat., 2te Aufl., Jena, 1900, S. 96.
It is brought up again by Lipps,[10] who assumes that the streak ought
to dart with the eyes and calls therefore the oppositely moving streak
the ‘falsely localized image.’ For sake of brevity we may call this
the ‘false image.’ The explanation of Lipps can be pieced together as
follows (ibid., S. 64): “The explanation presupposes that sensations
of eye-movements have nothing to do with the projection of retinal
impressions into the visual field, that is, with the perception of the
mutual relations as to direction and distance, of objects which are
viewed simultaneously…. Undoubtedly, however, sensations of
eye-movements, and of head-and body-movements as well, afford us a
scale for measuring the displacements which our entire visual field
and every point in it undergo within the surrounding _totality of
space_, which we conceive of as fixed. We estimate according to the
length of such movements, or at least we deduce therefrom, the
distance through fixed space which our view by virtue of these
movements has traversed…. They themselves are nothing for our
consciousness but a series of purely intensive states. But in
experience they can come to indicate distance traversed.” Now in
turning the eye from a luminous object, O, to some other
fixation-point, P, the distance as simply contemplated is more or
less subdivided or filled in by the objects which are seen to lie
between O and P, or if no such objects are visible the distance is
still felt to consist of an infinity of points; whereas the muscular
innervation which is to carry the eye over this very distance is an
undivided unit. But it is this which gives us our estimate of the arc
we move through, and being thus uninterrupted it will appear shorter
than the contemplated, much subdivided distance OP, just as a
continuous line appears shorter than a broken line. “After such
analogies, now, the movement of the eye from O to P, that is, the
arc which I traverse, must be underestimated” (ibid., S. 67). There
is thus a discrepancy between our two estimates of the distance OP.
This discrepancy is felt during the movement, and can be harmonized
only if we seem to see the two fixation-points move apart, until the
arc between them, in terms of innervation-feeling, feels equal to the
distance OP in terms of its visual subdivisions. Now either O and
P can both seem to move apart from each other, or else one can seem
fixed while the other moves. But the eye has for its goal P, which
ought therefore to have a definite position. “P appears fixed
because, as goal, I hold it fast in my thought” (_loc. citat._). It
must be O, therefore, which appears to move; that is, O must dart
backward as the eye moves forward toward P. Thus Lipps explains the
illusion.
[10] Lipps, Th., _Zeitschrift f. Psychologie u. Physiologie der
Sinnesorgane_, 1890, I., S. 60-74.
Such an explanation involves many doubtful presuppositions, but if we
were to grant to Lipps those, the following consideration would
invalidate his account. Whether the feeling of innervation which he
speaks of as being the underestimated factor is supposed to be a true
innervation-feeling in the narrower sense, or a muscular sensation
remembered from past movements, it would in the course of experience
certainly come to be so closely associated with the corresponding
objective distance as not to feel less than this. So far as an
innervation-feeling might allow us to estimate distance, it could have
no other meaning than to represent just that distance through which
the innervation will move the organ in question. If OP is a distance
and i is the feeling of such an innervation as will move the eye
through that distance, it is inconceivable that i, if it represent
any distance at all, should represent any other distance than just
OP.
Cornelius[11] brought up the matter a year later than Lipps. Cornelius
criticises the unwarranted presuppositions of Lipps, and himself
suggests that the falsely localized streak is due to a slight rebound
which the eye, having overshot its intended goal, may make in the
opposite direction to regain the mark. This would undoubtedly explain
the phenomenon if such movements of rebound actually took place.
Cornelius himself does not adduce any experiments to corroborate this
account.
[11] Cornelius, C.S., _Zeitschrift f. Psychologie u.
Physiologie der Sinnesorgane_, 1891, II., S. 164-179.
The writer, therefore, undertook to find out if such movements
actually are made. The observations were made by watching the eyes of
several subjects, who looked repeatedly from one fixation-point to
another. Although sometimes such backward movements seemed indeed to
be made, they were very rare and always very slight. Inasmuch as the
‘false’ streak is often one third as long as the distance moved
through, a movement of rebound, such as Cornelius means, would have to
be one third of the arc intended, and could therefore easily have been
noticed. Furthermore, the researches of Lamansky,[12] Guillery,[13]
Huey,[14] Dodge and Cline,[15] which are particularly concerned with
the movements of the eyes, make no mention of such rebounds.
Schwarz[16] above all has made careful investigations on this very
point, in which a screen was so placed between the observer and the
luminous spot that it intervened between the pupil and the light, just
before the end of the movement. Thus the retina was not stimulated
during the latter part of its movement, just when Cornelius assumed
the rebound to take place. This arrangement, however, did not in the
least modify the appearance of the false streak.
[12] Lamansky, S., _Pflüger’s Archiv f. d. gesammte
Physiologie_, 1869, II., S. 418.
[13] Guillery, ibid., 1898, LXXI., S. 607; and 1898, LXXIII.,
S. 87.
[14] Huey, Edmund B., American Journal of Psychology, 1900,
XI., p. 283.
[15] Dodge, Raymond, and Cline, T.S., PSYCHOLOGICAL REVIEW,
1901, VIII., PP. 145-157.
[16] Schwarz, Otto, _Zeitschrift J. Psychologie u. Physiologie
der Sinnesorgane_, 1892, III., S. 398-404.
This work of Schwarz certainly proves that the explanation of
Cornelius is not correct. Schwarz found that the phenomenon takes
place as well when the head moves and the eyes are fixed relatively to
the head, as when the eyes alone move. He furthermore made this
observation. Meaning by a the point of departure and by b the goal
of either the eye-or the head-movement, movement, he says (ibid.,
S. 400-2): “While oftentimes the streak of the after-image extended
uninterruptedly to the point b, or better seemed to proceed from
this point,—as Lipps also reported—yet generally, under the
experimental conditions which I have indicated, two streaks could be
seen, separated by a dark space between; firstly the anomalous one”
(the false streak) “rather brilliant, and secondly a fainter one of
about equal or perhaps greater length, which began at the new
fixation-point b and was manifestly an after-image correctly
localized with regard to the situation of this point. This last
after-image streak did not always appear; but it appeared regularly if
the light at a was bright enough and the background dark…. It was
impossible for this second after-image streak to originate in the
point b, because it appeared equally when b was only an imaginary
fixation-point…. This consideration makes it already conceivable
that the two parts of the total after-image _are two manifestations of
the one identical retinal stimulation, which are differently
localized_…. Therefore we must probably picture to ourselves that
the sensation from the strip of the retina stimulated during the quick
eye-movement is, _during the interval of movement or at least during
the greater part of it, localized as if the axis of vision were still
directed toward the original fixation-point. And when the new position
of rest is reached and the disturbance on the retinal strip has not
wholly died away, then the strip comes once more into consciousness,
but this time correctly localized with reference to the new position
of the axis of vision_. By attending closely to the behavior as
regards time of both after-image streaks, I can generally see the
normal after-image develop a moment later than the anomalous one”
(that is, the false streak). Schwarz finally suggests (S. 404) that
probably between the first and second appearances of the streak an
‘innervation-feeling’ intervenes which affords the basis for
localizing the second streak (‘correctly’) with reference to the new
position of the eye.
After this digression we return to consider how this phenomenon is
related to the hypothesis of anæsthesia during eye-movements. If we
accept the interpretation of Schwarz, there is one retinal process
which is perceived as two luminous streaks in space, localized
differently and referred to different moments of time. It is
surprising, then, that a continuous retinal process is subjectively
interpreted as two quite different objects, that is, as something
discontinuous. Where does the factor of discontinuity come in? If we
suppose the retinal disturbance to produce a continuous sensation in
consciousness, we should expect, according to every analogy, that this
sensation would be referred to one continuously existing object. And
if this object is to be localized in two places successively, we
should expect it to appear to move continuously through all
intervening positions. Such an interpretation is all the more to be
expected, since, as the strobic phenomena show, even discontinuous
retinal processes tend to be interpreted as continuously existing
objects.
On the other hand, if there were a central anæsthesia during
eye-movement, the continuous process in the retina could not produce a
continuous sensation, and if the interval were long enough the image
might well be referred to two objects; since also, in the strobic
appearances, the stimulations must succeed at a certain minimal rate
in order to produce the illusion of continuous existence and movement.
This consideration seemed to make it worth while to perform some
experiments with the falsely localized after-images. The phenomenon
had also by chance been noted in the case of the eye moving past a
luminous dot which was being regularly covered and uncovered. The
appearance is of a row of luminous spots side by side in space, which
under conditions may be either falsely or correctly localized. Since
these dots seemed likely to afford every phenomenon exhibited by the
streaks, with the bare chance of bringing out new facts, apparatus was
arranged as in Fig. 1, which is a horizontal section.
DD is a disc which revolves in a vertical plane, 56 cm. in diameter
and bearing near its periphery one-centimeter holes punched 3 cm.
apart. E is an eye-rest, and L an electric lamp.
Comments (0)